Theatricality and Sincerity
In a short untitled piece collected in Discussions in Contemporary Culture from 19871, Michael Fried emphasises that his opposition to the theatricality of minimalist art, famously expressed in Art and Objecthood of 19672, was an opposition “limited to the [then] contemporary situation.”3 He says: Art and Objecthood’s claim is that theatricality was, in 1967, inimical to art as it was then. From the vantage point of 1987, he implies that he never had an absolute mistrust of theatricality; rather, this mistrust related to the specific period of the minimalism – or literalism, as he names it - of the 1960s.
Following the critical reception of the essay and in the light of Fried’s later work on absorption and theatricality (which we will come to below), is this merely special pleading after the event? In Art and Objecthood Fried does indeed twice link the corruption of minimalist art to the current moment: “theatre is now the negation of art”4; “theatre and theatricality are at war today…. with art as such”5. If critical readers have missed this temporal limitation to the argument, as the author complains, then this is perhaps not surprising given the trenchant quality of the piece and its apparent a-temporal tone elsewhere: the Objecthood of the literalists is “antithetical to art”6; “what is wrong with literalist work is… that it is… incurably theatrical”7; “…theatre’s profound hostility to the arts…”8; “… a sensibility already theatrical, already (to say the worst) corrupted or perverted by theatre”9; “Art degenerates as it approaches the condition of theatre.”10 Furthermore, as Hal Foster points out in The Crux of Minimalism11, Fried’s essay is framed by the absolute, by an appeal to God. The epigraph is a quotation from the Puritan theologian Jonathan Edwards and speaks of the “abiding assurance” of the presence of God. The final sentence is a “spiritual imperative” (in Foster’s words): “Presentness is grace”12. This is art criticism, or art theory, as theology. The attentive reader might be forgiven for coming away from the essay convinced of the absolute character of the argument, if not by the argument itself.
Let us however take Fried at his 1987 word and allow that the absolutist statements be read in the light of the temporally limited ones, and not vice versa. We should, of course, also read Art and Objecthood in the light of his later works on the history of French 18th and 19th century art, specifically Absorption and Theatricality (1980)13, Courbet’s Realism (1990)14 and Manet’s Modernism (1996)15 which incorporates his seminal essay Manet’s Sources, 1859-1869 from 1969.16 These books – each one located squarely within the discipline of art history – do not fail to cite Art and Objecthood, a work of art criticism which is outside the discipline of art history as such. The appeal in the later books to the earlier polemical essay is in each case an explanatory one: the reader is invited to refer back to the arguments against minimalism in order to clarify the context within which Fried analyses 18th and 19th century French painting. It is instructive to follow these references – both their tone and content.
In Absorption and Theatricality Fried repeats his polemical disparagement of minimalism as “seemingly difficult and advanced but actually ingratiating and mediocre”, and notes that, as the title of the book “makes clear, the concept of theatricality is crucial to my interpretation of French painting and criticism in the age of Diderot, and in general the reader who is familiar with my essays on abstract art will be struck by certain parallels between ideas developed in those essays and in this book.”17
A decade later, in Courbet’s Realism, the tone and content regarding minimalism is somewhat different: “As for the relation of this book to my writings on abstract painting and sculpture of the 1960s and early 1970s (in particular to the essay ''Art and Objecthood"), there is an important sense in which, like Absorption and Theatricality,it investigates the roots of what I characterized in 1966-67 as a new, decisive split within contemporary artistic practice.”18 The disparagement of minimalism is not repeated. Gone, too, is the 1967 idea that minimalism is not even art. Instead of a threat to art itself, minimalism now represents merely a dichotomy (albeit decisive) within the realm of art.
In the coda to Manet’s Modernism, Fried refers to a “final step in a formalist-modernist evolution [that] would purport to go beyond painting into Minimalist objecthood.” The depreciation of minimalism reappears with the word “purport”, but this time the act which minimalism carries out on art is neither to destroy it (the 1967 position), nor to split it (the 1980 position) but simply to contribute to its evolution.19
However, if in these books Fried refers us back to the essay in order to clarify his position on French painting, in turn their arguments clarify the idea of theatricality used previously in that essay. But before I come to these, I would like to look at what we can glean about theatricality in Fried at the time the essay was written. Rosalind Krauss, in a reading that is deconstructivist in technique – a style of critique Fried implies in 1996 is necessary in order to comprehend his aims in Art and Objecthood20 - holds that the central concept of theatricality is not anywhere defined:
Now the theatre and theatricality are precisely what is not defined in the pages of “Art and Objecthood,” or in the one definition that is ventured we are told that theatre is what lies between the arts, a definition that specifies theatre as a nonthing, an emptiness, a void. Theatre is thus an empty term whose role it is to set up a system founded upon the opposition between itself and another term. This is not of course a neutral, unloaded opposition, a simple a versus b, rather it is one that is vectored along an axis of good and bad: Theatre as the empty, unlocatable, amorphous member of the pair is bad, while the nontheatrical rises within the pair to be coded as good.21
This isolating of an empty term around which the analysis (and, supposedly, the piece itself) turns; the precipitation out of a binary pair of concepts; and the depreciation of one of those concepts represents a classic deconstructivist analysis, and Krauss notes that Derrida gives the name logocentrism to the strategy of thought thus deconstructed.22 Krauss is, however, too quick in her appeal to deconstructivist analysis. That Fried does not, in so many explicit words, state what theatricality is does not mean to say it is undefined within Art and Objecthood, or that it is specified as empty or void. This is something that I wish to insist on, because in fact theatricality has its own inherent positive character, as we will see. Within the contexts in which it is used here, theatricality has, for Fried, an utterly clear meaning:
Literalist sensibility is theatrical because, to begin with, it is concerned with the actual circumstances in which the beholder encounters the work… the experience of literalist art is of an object in a situation - one that virtually by definition, includes the beholder.23
Krauss is correct that, for Fried, the term ‘theatricality’ is opposed to another term or idea, namely the character of modernist painting which Fried insists has the status of real art; and that within the binary structure theatricality is depreciated. (As is well known, and as will be discussed below, theatricality is more generally opposed to the concept of absorption.) To claim in addition (or therefore) that the term theatricality is empty ignores the critical efforts that Fried makes to understand minimalism/literalism through this concept of theatricality, which he carefully characterises as something far from a Kraussian “void”.
Furthermore, an analysis of what theatricality means for Fried in the late 1960s cannot omit consideration of the last words of Art and Objecthood, which in the footnotes refer us to two essays by Stanley Cavell – readings of Shakespeare and Beckett – collected in 1969 in Must We Mean What We Say?”24 And when we read Cavell, what we find is a corresponding footnote which states:
That the place of art is now pervasively threatened by the production of objects whose hold upon us is theatrical, and that serious modernist art survives only in its ability to defeat theater, are companion subjects of Michael Fried’s “Art and Objecthood” (Artforum, Volume V, No. 10, June, 1967, pp. 12–23). It is, among other things, the most useful and enlightening explanation of the tastes and ambitions of the fashionable modern sensibility I know of. Its conjunction with what I am saying in this essay (even to the point of specific concepts, most notably that of “presentness’’) is more exact than can be made clear in a summary, and will be obvious to anyone reading it.25
As Fried has made clear elsewhere26, there is a to-and-fro between his critical and art historical writings and the ordinary language philosophy of his friend Cavell27, and as these two footnotes indicate, Fried has obtained his terms from and in discussion with Cavell. The very term “theatricality” comes from one of these essays - Cavell’s piece on Beckett entitled “Ending the Waiting Game”, which Fried notes that he read in 1963 or 1964.28
Pace Krauss, it is therefore not to Derrida or deconstruction that we should look for a hint, in the late 1960s, as to the sources or resources of Fried’s concept of theatricality, but rather to the ordinary language philosophy of Cavell, which he develops, as Bruns notes, out of late Ludwig Wittgenstein and J. L. Austin.29
This brings me to the first key point I wish to address: if we grant, as noted above, that Fried’s disparagement of theatricality was specific to the situation of the late 1960s in the United States, noting nonetheless that the way in which this supposedly (at least in retrospect, for Fried) relative concern gets expressed at times in an absolutist, arguably (with Foster) theological manner, then what is it about that moment which caused Fried to be so vehemently against minimalism? Foster has already, in The Return of the Real, noted that Fried’s objections relate to the “disciplinary basis of his formalist aesthetics”30 in that “the old Enlightenment order of the arts (the temporal versus the spatial arts) is endangered.”31 (I would note in passing, because it speaks to the argument later on, that Foster is wrong here to characterise Fried as a formalist critic. Fried is not Clement Greenberg, and he himself complains in places about being bracketed with formalists.32 More specifically, I would argue that Fried’s positive engagement with ordinary language philosophy and, as we will see, phenomenology, is precisely anti-formalist.33) The undermining of the disciplinary basis of art criticism and art history, and the overturning of the “old” (in Foster’s word) Enlightenment artistic order is clearly a challenge to Fried’s position within the discipline, as evident when he rather sniffily notes that “the literalists have largely avoided the issue of value or quality”34, a value or quality that Fried implies it is the task of critics such as him to decide, and in such a manner that the quality may not be “in doubt”.35 However, these disciplinary and personal issues still do not get to the crux of Fried’s vehemence, which cannot merely be an issue of a threat to his professional status.
If the link to Cavell is given the weight I believe it deserves, then we need to see the key terms of Fried’s argument – “theatricality” and “Presentness”, a Presentness which we have already noted has a theological aspect – in the light of ordinary language philosophy, and in the light of the issue of the sincerity of an utterance that that philosophy considers as a key question. For ordinary language philosophers, it is the seriousness with which an utterance is said which marks out its validity, and Cavell translates this characteristic across to the world of art when he states that “this means that modern art, if and where it exists, forces the issue of sincerity, depriving the artist and his audience of every measure except absolute attention to one’s experience and absolute honesty in expressing it.”36 That Fried takes sincerity seriously is evident from the preface to Manet’s Modernism, where he makes a claim for the sincerity of his argument, which he claims “is sincere in the sense of being the best that I can do under the circumstances.”37 This emphasis is his, as it is later on when he remarks upon Manet’s sincerity: “His pictures, he wrote in 1867, were above all sincere: ‘It's the effect of sincerity to give to works a character that makes them appear an act of protest, when the painter has thought only of rendering his impression.’”38 The themes of Presentness and presence (which Fried opposed to each other) also need to be read in the light of phenomenology, which Fried already makes reference to in his 1965 essay Three American Painters, where he notes that the work of Jackson Pollock, Morris Louis, Kenneth Noland, Jules Olitski and Frank Stella have a “phenomenological subtlety, complexity and richness without equal since Manet.”39 Later on, in Courbet’s Realism, Fried will state that “as a general emphasis [his analysis] is in line with the philosophical tendency known as existential phenomenology, and in fact a long-standing familiarity with phenomenological thinking (in particular with the work of Maurice Merleau Ponty) helped shape the approach of this study.”40
In taking Fried at his word that he is a phenomenologist, and in accepting that modernist art is phenomenological in its intent, I am making a counter-argument to Hal Foster’s claim that it is rather minimalism which uses the resources of phenomenological thought. He states in The Return of the Real that “minimalism turned from the objective orientation of formalism to the subjective orientation of phenomenology…”41 This is part and parcel of Foster’s claim that Fried is (with Greenberg) a formalist; this enables him to equate formalism with Fried’s modernism and then show minimalism as a phenomenological response to that formalism. My argument is instead that Fried analyses modernism through phenomenology, and that minimalism is, precisely, post-phenomenological. I believe Fried is right to link the work of high modernist painters with phenomenology, and this link enables Fried to make a more substantive analysis of their work than the formalism of Greenberg allows. But by the end of the 1960s, phenomenology, and with it ordinary language philosophy and Cavell’s concept of “Presentness”, were themselves under an existential threat, announced with the lecture “Structure, Sign, and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences” which introduced Derrida to the United States fifty years ago in October 1966.42
For, as is well known, what the early work of Derrida does is to question the basic premises of phenomenology, and particularly the notion of presence. In the lecture cited above, for instance, Derrida contrasts the concept of play – radical play, play without foundation – with that of presence, and notes that “Play is the disruption of presence”.43 We cannot begin our analysis, he states, with something like presence; rather, it is on the basis of the non-presence of play that something like the alternative between presence and absence can be established. To set out one’s analysis on the basis of a positive term such as “presence” or “Presentness”, as Fried does, can only be justified by an appeal to an absolute position, in other words by an appeal to God or via the resources of theology. We have already noted that Foster notes that this is exactly what Fried does at the beginning and end of Art and Objecthood. For Derrida, the basis of any valid discussion must be not a positive term such as presence, but rather the hyper-relational situation of différance. As Derrida’s essay of that name says, “What is written as différance, then, will be the playing movement that ‘produces’…. these differences, these effects of difference.”44
Krauss’s characterisation of deconstructive analysis, cited above, as positing an empty “void” around which binary concepts are organised and ordered is therefore doubly wrong: not only is Fried’s notion of the theatrical not empty (as I have shown, Fried defines it in positive terms), but deconstruction operates on the basis of the fullness and “affirmation” (as Derrida says, in Nietzschean terms) of play45, not the emptiness of the void. Nonetheless, Krauss’s caricature of deconstructive analysis is pertinent here, because although Derrida was at pains from the outset to emphasize the excessive affirmation of deconstruction, this was not how his work was generally understood by Anglo-Saxon philosophers and human scientists. Rather, the challenge to phenomenological presence, outlined explicitly in Derrida’s work on Husserl46, and the challenge to the presence implied by ordinary language philosophy, outlined in Derrida’s essay on Austin47 and later expanded in Limited Inc48 was regarded for a number of decades as being nothing less than a challenge to all rational thought and to Enlightenment order, instead of being seen for what it really was – a response to Nietzsche’s death of God and an analysis of the impossibility of founding concepts if theology is deemed to have lost its purchase.
If I am correct in this – and it is difficult to believe that Fried, and Cavell, in using the terms “presence” and “Presentness” to inform the notion of (non-?) artistic theatricality, would not have been doing so at that time in conscious counter-point to the new and disruptive influence of Derrida on the American scene – then that explains the ostensibly odd Puritan theological epigraph to Art and Objecthood. The antidote to a Derridean and European lack of presence is the invocation of the faith of an archetypal New World Puritan. And if Fried was later to claim that a deconstructive reading of his text was welcome, as we have already noted, then this reflects less an acceptance of différance and more an acknowledgement that the discourse of the human sciences in the States had by that time generally reduced the efficacy and purchase of Derrida’s attempted destruction of metaphysics – as evidenced by Krauss’s caricature of it.49
What follows from this is a point about minimalist art itself. If, with Fried, we can say that the high modernists, against which the minimalists (principally Donald Judd and Robert Morris) positioned themselves, were essentially concerned with phenomenology in their work, then in turn minimalism necessarily becomes a critique not just of a Friedian modernism, but also of its philosophical underpinnings. In other words, minimalism is anti-phenomenological; and that is what Fried is pointing to when he states that the “presence” of the minimalist work is to be opposed to the “Presentness” of true art, exemplified by the modernist painters and sculptors he championed. This is not to argue that the minimalists were necessarily indebted to Derrida; I see no sign of this in their writings of that time. However, Derrida was only one sign, in the 1960s, of the overturning of the modernist tenets of presence, albeit one that most obviously pitched its tent against that metaphysical founding concept. In order to say more about this, I will look at the concrete terms of Fried’s argument in Art and Objecthood, informed also by his later writings on theatricality.
For what, after all, is the theatrical for Fried? The most straightforward way to characterise it, although somewhat anachronistic in relation to Art and Objecthood, is to contrast it with absorption, a term which Fried famously takes from Denis Diderot in Absorption and Theatricality. Absorption is clearly a phenomenological term, for Fried: the first chapter of that book is entitled “The Primacy of Absorption”, a clear reference to Merleau-Ponty’s The Primacy of Perception which as we have already seen was influential on Fried.50 The theory of theatricality can be said to rotate around Diderot’s claim, cited by Fried in the original French, that a painting is sublime – is a great painting - “qu'il n'y a personne au monde que les personnages du tableau".51 We can translate this phrase from Diderot as “there is no one else in the world except the people in the tableau”. This is the mark of absorption: that within the tableau of the painting – that is, within the scene (tableau) that it represents - the people shown will be totally absorbed in their activities, in the scene within which they are depicted. Famously, for Fried as for Diderot, the drama of the tableau, its unity as presented by the skill of the painter, is what makes for great art, and it is in this sense that the notion of absorption relies upon the phenomenological concept of presence: the people depicted in the scene must appear to be wholly present to each other.
Theatricality, by contrast, occurs when the people within the scene do not appear to be wholly absorbed by what they are doing, by their interrelations with each other, and the prime cause for the disruption of absorption is the situation where the characters in the scene begin to relate not only (or at all) to each other, but instead to the “beholder” (as Fried names it) who is looking at the painting. For Diderot, this disruption of the absorption of the represented characters in the name of a theatricality is the mark of bad painting, and it is this 18th century notion of theatricality which Fried takes up in his analysis of minimalism in Art and Objecthood. So, the term theatricality should not be taken to refer in general to the theatre, but rather to the specific moment when any art makes an explicit appeal to its audience. Bad theatricality (for Diderot and the Fried of Art and Objecthood) is to be contrasted with the good quality of drama, for drama is what happens within the represented scene or tableau such that it remains a world unto itself, such that the characters therein remain absorbed in themselves and do not relate outwards, so not open themselves up to the audience or “beholder” (to use Fried’s term).
I would like to make a second key point, in relation to Fried’s analysis of Diderot and French 19th century painting, before we return to minimalism. Fried, in Absorption and Theatricality and elsewhere, characterises the issue of theatricality as a paradox. Amongst other places, he notes in the introduction that Diderot works in his writings with a “paradoxical relationship between painting and beholder”52; there is a paradox inherent in Jean-Baptiste Greuze’s paintings53 which also works over those of Jean-Baptiste-Siméon Chardin54; in Courbet’s Realism he again notes “a new and paradoxical relationship between the work of art and its audience.”55 What exactly is this paradox, and why does it become such for Fried? There is a remarkable point towards the end of the first chapter of Absorption and Theatricality where he makes an appeal to the reader:
It has become clear, I think, that the developments analysed in this chapter [regarding Greuze and other painters] involve a major shift in the relationship between painting and beholder.56
And it is this shift which has a “paradoxical” quality, a quality which lies in the fact that the drama of the painting – the quality of the absorption of the represented characters in each other’s presence – is a denial of the “basic” fact of the beholder’s presence to the painting, the fact that the beholder is looking at what is going on in the painting. This “basic fact” is, at one level, the phenomenon of theatricality. As Fried states in Courbet’s Realism, “the theatrical” is in one sense “a basic pictorial or ontological category.”57 By this he means the simple fact that all paintings, and all art, are made to be looked at. Therefore, the paradox lies in the way in which the “dramatic” art which Diderot valued denied this “basic” theatricality. Given that, for Fried (at least most of the time) as for Diderot, theatrical work is not in fact art, one can say that all art worthy of the name is for them paradoxical in this sense. Pliny was wrong: Zeuxis’ painting of grapes trumps the trompe-l'œil curtain of Parrhasius, since the former makes a theatrical appeal only to the birds, not to us.
Note that what Fried does here is to elide the logical distinction between the scene of the painting, the “tableau” that it represents, and the painting itself as a work. If that distinction is elided, then art tends to become, essentially, a question of representation: no distinction is made between what the painting represents and what it is. Having discussed at length the drama of the paintings of Chardin, Grueze and others – that is, the way in which the scenes which these paintings depict become more absorptive, and the fact this this absorption is explicitly praised by Diderot in his critical writings, Fried then states baldly in the quotation cited above that this concerns “the relationship between painting and beholder”. This is not strictly speaking correct: it concerns rather the relationship between the tableau of the painting and the beholder, which is an entirely different thing.
As Stephen Melville and others have pointed out, the French word tableau means both painting and the scene which is represented in the painting.58 We can therefore say that Diderot has some excuse when he elides the difference between a painting and what is represented in the painting by stating that “En supposant qu'd n'y a personne au monde que les personnages du tableau, celui de Vandick est sublime.”59 In Fried’s translation this reads: “In supposing that there is no one else in the world except the personages of the painting, Van Dyck's painting is sublime.”60 We may excuse Diderot for using this ambiguity, or we might alternatively note that it is the disregarding of this ambiguity which sets up the deliberate naivety of the notion of “classicism”, of the notion of the classical in painting (and elsewhere).61 For Fried, the maintenance of the equivalence between the two meanings of tableau is symptomatic of his view of art as an essentially representational exercise. It is this essentially representational quality of art which Fried does not want to let go of (and which again marks him out as anything but a formalist) and which is at the root, I argue, of his avowed aversion to minimalist art. This may on the face of it appear a strange assertion to make of someone who places in contrast to minimalism the work of the abstract painters already mentioned, or the work of sculptors such as Anthony Caro. However, the terms in which Fried speaks of these works in Art and Objecthood makes clear that he does not conceive them outside the realm of representation.
He does this by making an analogy between the character of, say, a Caro sculpture and the narrative structure of an 18th century French painting. The absorptive quality of the drama of the painting has its equivalent, for Fried, in the drama of the internal structure of a Caro sculpture, a structure and set of relations which he claims can be apprehended all at once in a moment of Presentness: and this “Presentness is grace”.62 Although the good, modernist work of art has a complex structure – for instance, the complexity of the relations between the elements of a sculpture by Caro or David Smith, just as for Diderot a good painting has a complex structure inherent in the drama unfolding within the tableau – it therefore also has the quality of “presentness and instantaneousness”. There is a moment of presentness, there is an instantaneous absorption of a proper work of art, evident when Fried asserts that the modernist work, or the true work of art, is “wholly manifest” at every moment; or when he says that it has a quality of instantaneousness.63 Fried posits this notion of presentness, and the instant, in order to maintain the distinction he wishes to draw between the avowedly time-based work of the minimalists and the modernists he favours. But he also has to maintain it because he remains within a representational concept of art. The internal dispositif64 or machine of Caro’s work65, its dramatic quality, has a representational quality which the minimalists identify as anthropomorphic; this work is a body, to use Antonin Artaud’s term, with organs. As Fried says, Caro’s work has “meaning”, and it defeats objecthood “by imitating, not gesture exactly, but the efficacy of gesture.”66 And by contrast the trouble with the minimalist work is that it does not “represent, signify or allude to anything”.67
Likewise, in his 2011 return to art criticism Four Honest Outlaws: Sala, Ray, Marioni, Gordon68, Fried is at pains to emphasize that the subjective experience of the viewer of these works does not become the work itself (as in minimalism/literalism), but rather matters because that experience provides “a channel of insight into the overall structure of intentions that make the work what it is”.69 So even in the case of ostensibly abstract works such as Joseph Marioni’s, Fried’s concern is to show, by patient analysis of the making of the work – a making which he does not fail to note gives a distinctly non-minimalist “composite” quality to the paintings70 - how the structure of intentions of the artist is conveyed to the beholder. It is in this sense that Fried’s concept of art remains representational: art is the transmission of a certain meaningful structure across to the subject that views the work, be this structure the physical layers of paint in Marioni or the absorption evident in the subject matter of Anri Sala’s video pieces. This is why the sincerity of the work or, as the title of the book implies, its honesty as a true and authentic attempt to convey something to the beholder, is so important to Fried; a lack of sincerity or honesty implies the undermining of the schema of representation.
By contrast, it is the essentially anti-representational (and therefore anti-aesthetic) nature of art, its ontological status outside the realm of representation, which the best writers on minimalism, cited by Fried, posit. Exemplary (but not alone) in this regard is Tony Smith’s anecdote of his experience on the New Jersey Turnpike, quoted at length in Art and Objecthood:
This drive was a revealing experience. The road and much of the landscape was artificial, and yet it couldn’t be called a work of art. On the other hand, it did something for me that art had never done. At first I didn’t know what it was, but its effect was to liberate me from many of the views I had had about art. It seemed that there had been a reality there that had not had any expression in art.
The experience on the road was something mapped out but not socially recognized. I thought to myself, it ought to be clear that’s the end of art. Most painting looks pretty pictorial after that. There is no way you can frame it, you just have to experience it.71
On the one hand Smith is stating an experience that he says lies outside art; on the other hand, what he is doing is redefining art as it had heretofore been defined. No longer is art to be pictorial; that is, no longer is art to be seen as essentially to do with representation and meaning, as Fried would have it. Rather, art is to do with the experience – a real experience - and this experience, Smith says, has not previously had any “expression” in art. It becomes the specific task of minimalism to express the reality which had been apprehended in this experience. Smith is making a statement about the ontology of the art work, and the ontology he is positing and then promoting is an anti-representational one.
This anti-representational quality is precisely summed up by Fried’s notion of theatricality. If, as noted above, the internal dispositif or machine of a work like Caro’s has a relational quality that can be analysed (just as Fried analyses the drama of French 18th century painting, or a video piece by Sala, or the composite layered structure of a Marioni painting), a body with organs where the organs can be separated out, then what minimalism does is to posit instead, or in addition, what we might call an external dispositif or machine.72 This external dispositif is also relational; it is the relation of theatricality which Fried has correctly identified as the key concept of minimalism. We could say that the minimalist work of art is therefore a “body without organs”, in the terms in which Artaud would understand that. What minimalism points to is a change in the perceived ontology of the work of art, and it is this change which stimulates Fried’s vehemence, it is this challenge which he feels he must oppose in the strongest terms as being the destruction of art.
This minimalist or literalist ontology of art is an essentially relational ontology. What the minimalist work does is to foreground and express the relation between not only those who come to view it and live with it – to experience it - but also the specific situation in which it exists. The best works of minimalism are situational works; for Fried, this is a marker of their lack of quality, their lack of authenticity,73 but this lack of quality is such only when looked at from the point of view of a representational and “meaningful” ontology of art.
What is remarkable about this new relational ontology of art that Smith in particular, and minimalism in general, puts forward is that it picks up on the trajectory of thought and philosophy which goes beyond Fried’s phenomenology and Cavell’s ordinary language philosophy. I have already outlined what I see as Fried’s implicit opposition to deconstruction in Art and Objecthood, where the central theme of presence or presentness is directly counter to the play of différance which Derrida announces. But what is the play of différance if not an essentially relational ontology? Différance expresses a sort of hyper-relationality. What différance says is that difference is primary, in other words that relations are primary, as long as we understand that the terms of the relation do not pre-exist the relation. It is the relation which is generative, not the positive terms of that relation, which are in fact an after-effect of the play of difference, of the play of relations.
Now Fried, of course, does not ignore this play between the art work and what he calls the “beholder”. In fact, it is something he mentions frequently, as we noted above. But he mentions it not in order to draw a conclusion about the ontology of the work of art, but rather, as we have seen, to dwell in the apparent paradox of the disjunction between the fact that certain works of art – those favoured by Diderot, for instance - appear to ignore this relation by concentrating on the internal drama of the tableau, and the fact that nonetheless this representational scene is being looked at by somebody. What minimalism claims, together with the philosophies that I am now outlining, is that the simplicity of the reality of the inevitable interplay between the work of art and those who come to it – an inevitability which Fried repeatedly and positively acknowledges – is nothing other than the reality of the work of art; this is its ontology, because this is what is common to all works of art, whether or not on an “ontical” level (as Heidegger might have expressed it) the work deals with that issue by being explicitly theatrical in the way in which Fried characterises it.
What is on the face of it puzzling about Fried’s vehement dislike of theatricality in Art and Objecthood is that sometimes in his writings he appears to have nothing against theatricality per se. As I noted at the outset, his opposition to theatricality was an opposition “limited to the [then] contemporary situation.”74 He recognises in turn that Diderot’s opposition to the theatricality of Rococo painting is an opposition that relates to its specific time. Fried does not rule that the theatricality of rococo painting means that all rococo painting is bad; nor does he rule that Manet’s work is poor painting because of its extraordinary theatrical quality – quite the opposite, although there is not enough space here to analyse the precise terms in which he does this.75 What I want to argue is that his vehemence is a result of the minimalist translation of theatricality out of the realm of representation – a realm which, as we have seen, Fried regards as containing the ontology of the work of art – and into the question of the ontology of the work, an alternative and anti-representational ontology which appears to directly challenge the whole basis on which Fried considers works of art.
I wish to conclude by pointing to the wider implications of this anti-representational ontology of the work of art. These questions occur not just in the supposedly limited realm of aesthetics, but more broadly they concern how we view the world and how the very notions of authenticity and sincerity with which we negotiate our social world are framed. I implied above that Fried’s concern for sincerity, filtered as it was through ordinary language philosophy and linked to the theological idea of the Presentness of grace, is marked as antithetical to theatricality, and yet that most theatrical of painters – Manet – was quoted approvingly in his sincerity by Fried. Sincerity and authenticity cannot, therefore, even in Fried, be regarded as determined in opposition to the acknowledgement of the interplay of theatre. What, therefore, is the place of sincerity in a world of différance, within an ontology of relations which come before any positing of the terms which make up those relations? We should note again that sincerity is an inherently representational issue for Fried. To be sincere means to aim to properly represent what is going on “inside”, to properly represent the essence of who one is, just as the good work of non-minimalist art, for Fried, and non-rococo art for Diderot, properly represented, without disruption, an internal drama, scene, or tableau.
With the destruction of this representational scene within art comes, if we take its full implications, the destruction of the representational qualities of the person. Fried was correct in his vehemence, in the sense that he sensed that the new ontology of the work of art which minimalism proclaims has much wider implications. Art, Fried (and with him Cavell) understood, is not a regional discipline, and at bottom the ontology of the work of art is necessarily the ontology of the world itself and our relation to it and to others. He did not wish to see us condemned to a universalising theatricality which would, in his terms, displace us from presence and give us no access to who we truly are – and therefore no access to sincerity. And his solution to this problem appears to involve the invocation of a godhead who will guarantee this presence and allow us access – if only at the limit or as an ideal – to a proper expression of ourselves.
If there is an answer to this question, then it would seem to me to lie in one of two directions. On the one hand, the question of sincerity – and much else – would need to be reframed in terms other than that of representation. It would then be necessary to think sincerity within the breach that minimalism signifies, within an ontology of relations, which in turn would mean to think sincerity beyond the question of identity. Alternatively, the concept of sincerity would become a question no longer posed; together with representation, it would disappear as a problem because the network of concepts which supports it has reached a point of crisis which tips discourse across a threshold into another set of guiding concepts. In reality, these two alternatives amount to the same thing, but we can say that the crisis of representation which precedes them is, in the realm of art, nowhere better displayed than in the twists and turns of Fried’s writings.
1 Michael Fried, Untitled essay, in Discussions in Contemporary Culture Number One, ed. Hal Foster (New York: Dia Art Foundation, 1987), 55-58.
2 Michael Fried, “Art and Objecthood”, Artforum (June 1967): 12-23. Collected in Michael Fried, Art and Objecthood: Essays and Reviews (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998), 148-172.
3 Fried, Untitled essay, 57.
4 Fried, “Art and Objecthood”, 153.
5 Ibid., 163.
6 Ibid., 153.
7 Ibid., 157.
8 Ibid., 160.
9 Ibid., 161.
10 Ibid., 164.
11 Hal Foster, “The Crux of Minimalism”, chapter two in The Return of the Real (Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1996), 52.
12 Fried, “Art and Objecthood”, 168.
13 Michael Fried, Absorption and Theatricality: Painting and Beholder in the Age of Diderot (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980).
14 Michael Fried, Courbet’s Realism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990).
15 Michael Fried, Manet’s Modernism or, The Face of Painting in the 1860s (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996).
16 Michael Fried, “Manet’s Sources: Aspects of his Art, 1859-1865,” Artforum 7 (March 1969): 28-82.
17 Fried, Absorption and Theatricality, 5.
18 Fried, Courbet’s Realism, 51.
19 This analysis of the references back to Art and Objecthood could of course be extended through many of Fried’s essays, for instance “Jeff Wall, Wittgenstein, and the Everyday”, Critical Inquiry 33 (Spring 2007): 495-526. The question of theatricality orientates all of Fried’s writing.
20 Fried, Untitled essay, 56.
21 Krauss, Untitled essay, in Discussions in Contemporary Culture Number One, 63.
22 Ibid., 63.
23 Fried, “Art and Objecthood”, 153.
24 Stanley Cavell, “Ending the Waiting Game” and “The Avoidance of Love: A Reading of King Lear” in Must We Mean What We Say? (updated edition: Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 115-162 and 267-353.
25 Cavell, Must We Mean What We Say?, 307 (footnote 16).
26 For instance, in Courbet’s Realism, 278-282, where the topic of theatricality is applied to photography, and Roland Barthes is brought into the discussion as someone who also addresses this question; in the same book page 334 on questions of activity and passivity; page 363 where Cavell’s notion of “nextness” in relation to Henry David Thoreau’s Walden is discussed; and in Absorption and Theatricality, page 182, where Fried states “Between Cavell's work and my own there exists a community of concept and purpose which will be apparent to anyone reading us both.” In the introduction to the book Manet’s Sources, Fried states that the original essay of the same title dating from 1969 was read by Cavell and discussed with him, and was indeed dedicated to him (page xviii). Fried’s book Realism, Writing, Disfiguration: On Thomas Eakins and Stephen Crane (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987) was also dedicated to Cavell.
27 See Fried, Untitled essay, 57, where he speaks of his “friendship with the philosopher Stanley Cavell.”
28 Michael Fried, ‘On Meeting Stanley Cavell’, MLN, vol. 126, no. 5, December 2011, 939–42.
29 Gerald L. Bruns, “Stanley Cavell's Shakespeare”, Critical Inquiry (issue 3 1990): 613.
30 Foster, The Return of the Real, 54.
31 Ibid., 52.
32 As Fried states in the first chapter of Courbet’s Modernism, “I don't think of my approach in this book (or in Absorption and Theatricality) as in any sense 'formalist:' an epithet that has tended mechanically to be affixed to my work ever since the 1960s….” Fried, Courbet’s Modernism, 47.
33 An example of this is given in Fried’s Manet’s Modernism, where he outlines Clement Greenberg’s “formalist” argument in relation to Manet’s modernism, but then notes that he himself finds this approach open to “serious objection.” Fried, Manet’s Modernism, 14.
34 Fried, “Art and Objecthood”, 164.
35 Ibid., 165.
36 Cavell, Must We Mean What We Say?, 195.
37 Fried, Manet’s Modernism, xxvi.
38Ibid., 23.
39 Fried, Art and Objecthood: Essays and Reviews, 223.
40 Fried, Courbet’s Realism, 49.
41 Foster, The Return of the Real, 59.
42 Jacques Derrida, “Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences”, in Writing and Difference, trans. Alan Bass (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978), 278-293.
43 Derrida, “Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences”, 292.
44 Jacques Derrida, “Différance” in Margins of Philosophy, trans. Alan Bass (Brighton: The Harvester Press, 1982), 11.
45 Derrida, “Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences”, 292.
46 Jacques Derrida, Speech and Phenomena and other essays on Husserl’s theory of signs, trans. David B. Allison (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1973).
47 Derrida, “Signature Event Context”, 307-330.
48 Jacques Derrida, Limited Inc, trans. Samuel Weber (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1988). The essay Limited Inc a b c… was first published in 1977 in Glyph.
49 What I am not able to do within the scope of this essay is to link Fried’s notion of theatricality with that of Artaud, whom he mentions on occasion. That reading would necessarily have to go via an analysis of Derrida’s essay “The Theatre of Cruelty”, where again Artaud is shown to deconstruct theatre into the infinite movement of play. Jacques Derrida, “The Theatre of Cruelty”, in Writing and Difference, trans. Alan Bass (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978), 232-250.
50 Maurice Merleau-Ponty, “The Primacy of Perception and its Philosophical Consequences”, in The Primary of Perception And Other Essays on Phenomenological Psychology, the Philosophy of Art, History and Politics, trans. James M. Edie (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1964), 12-42.
51 Fried, Absorption and Theatricality, 159.
52 Ibid., 3.
53 Ibid., 68.
54 Ibid., 103.
55 Fried, Courbet’s Realism, 6.
56 Fried, Absorption and Theatricality, 66.
57 Fried, Courbet’s Realism, 20.
58 See for instance Stephen Melville, “Notes on the Reemergence of Allegory, the Forgetting of Modernism, the Necessity of Rhetoric, and the Conditions of Publicity in Art and Criticism”, October, Vol. 19 (Winter, 1981), 55-92. Fried makes specific and warm reference to this essay as one which does, for him, address Art and Objecthood in a deconstructive manner (see Fried, Untitled essay, 58). I do not have the space here to show why Melville is not in fact using the strategies of deconstruction, but if I did then my argument would circle around the point that deconstruction does not have anything to do with arguments, like those of Fried, which use a misplaced notion of paradox to construct a discourse.
59 Diderot, Correspondance, IV, 57.
60 Fried, Absorption and Theatricality, 148.
61 This topic of the naivety of classicism comes up a number of times in Absorption and Theatricality, for instance in relation to the Abbé Laugier’s art criticism (Ibid., 15).
62 Fried, “Art and Objecthood”, 166-168.
63 Ibid., 167.
64 To use a term taken from Fried’s essay on Anri Sala. Michael Fried, Four Honest Outlaws: Sala, Ray, Marioni, Gordon (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2011), 62.
65 To use a term of Diderot’s which Fried quotes: “The principal idea [of a painting] properly conceived, must exercise its despotism over all the others. It is the driving force of the machine, which, like the force that maintains the celestial bodies in their orbits and carries them along, acts in inverse ratio to distance.” Fried, Absorption and Theatricality, 85.
66 Fried, “Art and Objecthood”, 162.
67 Ibid., 165.
68 Fried, Four Honest Outlaws. The essays in the book date from lectures he gave in 2008.
69 Ibid., 6.
70 Ibid., 140.
71 Tony Smith, quoted without specific reference in Fried, “Art and Objecthood”, 158.
72 I noted above that Fried uses the words “machine” (from Diderot) and dispositif in his writings. When he uses these terms, they always refer to a movement or complexity within the work of art. What I am pointing to here is a use of these terms that goes beyond the work of art precisely to include within its machinic workings the beholder or indeed the social field within which the art occurs. This use of these terms one can find in Deleuze and (in the case of dispositif) in Foucault.
73 Fried, “Art and Objecthood”, 167.
74 Fried, Untitled essay, in Discussions in Contemporary Culture Number One, 57.
75 See Fried, Manet’s Modernism, chapter three.